(Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Any topics primarily focused on metaphysics can be discussed here, in a generally casual way, where conversations may take unexpected turns.
User avatar
AshvinP
Posts: 5457
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 5:00 am
Location: USA

(Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by AshvinP »

Image



“We must not forget that nine-tenths of the words comprising the vocabulary of a civilised nation are never used by more than at most one tenth of the population; while of the remaining tithe, nine-tenths of those who use them are commonly aware of about one-tenth of their meanings.”
- Owen Barfield, History in English Words (1953)


Owen Barfield wrote a history of Western culture by doing nothing apart from following the origins and transformations of English words. In this endeavor, Barfield approached history in a very unique way. He perceived how the presence, absence, and use of various words, in relation to that of other words, could provide clear knowledge of Western civilization to someone otherwise ignorant of it. Not only that, but it could provide us a more objectively valid, living, and qualitative knowledge of this evolving history than all of the prosaic accounts taught by professors to students in universities. Barfield remarked, "It has only just begun to dawn on us that in our own language alone, not to speak of its many companions, the past history of humanity is spread out in an imperishable map, just as the history of the mineral earth lies embedded in the layers of its outer crust. But there is this difference between the record of the rocks and the secrets which are hidden in language: whereas the former can only give us a knowledge of outward, dead things—such as forgotten seas and the bodily shapes of prehistoric animals and primitive men—language has preserved for us the inner, living history of man's soul. It reveals the evolution of consciousness."

It is true that language provides an imperishable map of inner experience, but that is even more true of the sensible perceptions in the world which all language is drawn from. Barfield, and one of his favorite poets, Ralph Waldo Emerson, pointed attention often to the fact that all language we currently use to symbolize inner mental states and dispositions began as words reflecting the perceptible appearances of the world. Emerson observed, "Right originally means straight; wrong means twisted. Spirit primarily means wind; transgression, the crossing of a line; supercilious, the raising of the eye-brow." This ideal quality of physical images has not disappeared, but has only been veiled by our own abstract and limited cognition. One major obstacle to examining the transformations of perceptions, as opposed to words, is that most people cannot access perceptions beyond a very limited range of their recent memory. There is another approach, however, which can still yield fruit. We can start with our current perceptual experiences and see what those disclose to us about the phenomena in question, which, in this case, is the mechanisms of modern human culture and daily life. To begin with what presents itself to our experience most immediately is the genuinely phenomenological approach.



“All conscious nature has experiences of pleasure and pain. Man alone can deliberately will the repetition of an experience. And repetition, experienced as such, is at the heart, for good and evil, of his faculty of reasoning, and thus makes possible his language, his art, his morality, and indeed his humanity. Yet it is the enemy of life, for repetition is itself the principle, not of life but of mechanism.”
-Owen Barfield, Orpheus: A Poetic Drama



The willing of repetitive experience is also what we call Thinking and Memory. That is why Barfield places it at the very foundation of so many qualities which make us uniquely human. How can such qualities, which ground our speech, our reasoning intellect, our art, and our morality, then transform into "the enemy of life"? A famous philosopher once said, "evil is truth which is out of season". Many riddles surrounding the current state of humanity in the modern age can be understood through the lens of this simple Wisdom. Specifically, for our purposes here, the enemy of life arrives when this unique human quality of repetitive experiencing, which underlies all technological development in the modern age, is clinged to for the conveniences and comforts it provides long past their 'expiration date'. This stubborn refusal to evolve with the currents of cognition - this deeply ingrained desire to constantly swim upstream against them - then compounds itself into something which carries much more tragic consequences for humanity as a whole, the longer it is ignored and festers within us. We will see how those consequences have already unfolded in modern society and are still unfolding around us in due course. First, Barfield takes us back to the Reinassance era, when many of the predecessors to our current English vocabulary were reintroduced into the streams of Western thought.


Barfield wrote:The new intercourse with the ancient literatures of Greece and Rome naturally brought into English a positive stream of ‘literary borrowings’. At first these were mostly Latin words. If we try to imagine an English from which such words as accommodate, capable, capacious, compute, corroborate, distinguish, efficacy, estimate, experiment, insinuate, investigate, and a host of others equally common are as yet absent, we may partly realize what an important part was played by the Renaissance in producing the language in which we speak and think.


At this very early stage, there was still a feeling for the concrete experiences to which these words referred. At the end of the 17th century, a "computer" was still a human being "who calculates... whose occupation is to make arithmetical calculations". By the end of the 19th century, we first get its usage as a "calculating machine" with its own existence independent of any particular human being. It is only in 1937, through the personality of Alan Turing, that the word is first used in its modern sense of "programmable digital electronic device for performing mathematical or logical operations". One should clearly sense the distancing that is occurring here from the human body-brain and its living cognitive processes. The philosophical meaning of "abstract" as a verb from the mid-16th century is, "to draw away, withdraw, remove".  Let us be clear - for human thinking to draw away from nature and its processes was absolutely necessary for any modern technology to develop, such as that which I am taking advantage of now. We only fool ourselves if we imagine that we could have done without the Wisdom of this process. Yet our clear thinking should remain equally clear as we explore, in precise and concrete terms, what qualities of living experience we have also forsaken in this abstracting process of the modern mechanical age.

Mechanical technology itself is not unique to the modern age. What is unique is how this technology has influenced every dimension of our cultural existence, right down to the way we perceive and think about the world around us. It is not only our ideas about the world which have taken on a mechanical nature, but our method of forming ideas has been mechanized. That is what Barfield refers to above as "consciousness"; the generally subconscious way in which we perceive and cognize the World Content. Our considerations here will be supplemented by some of Barfield's findings along the way, but we will focus mostly on the digital age of technology which has only come into widespread use over the last few decades after Barfield's passing. Since the dawn of the 21st century, this technology has come to govern every sphere of our lives from our mornings to our evenings, our weekdays to our weekends, and our youth to our adulthood. It dictates our decisions in our homes and offices, in our cities and countrysides, and in our social, civic, personal, and professional lives. Based on his writings and the spirit of his thought more generally, it is a safe bet that Barfield would be very concerned with the accelerating pace of this development.

Many modern psychology books, articles, YouTube channels, and podcasts have tried to explore the harmful effects of digital technology. These analyses of the situtation paint with very broad strokes, thereby remaining hoplessly abstract and mostly unhelpful. The mechanization phenomena is treated as one more in a long list of bad habits, like smoking or eating fast food. It is referred to as yet another activity that people in the modern world should either avoid altogether or use in moderation to whatever extent possible. These approaches cannot possibly be helpful because they fail to diagnose the problem we are dealing with in its living essence. The task of any genuine "phenomenology" is to observe and deeply contemplate how these underlying living dynamics of the phenomena manifest in our immanent experience. We start with the phenomenal appearances - in this case, various aspects of digital technology - but we don't arbitarily end with the mere appearances if we can go further and deeper through sound logical reasoning. It is by penetrating into the depths of phenomena that we begin to actually hear their tales and tunes, otherwise muted, at first only by faint whispers, but later through resounding words, images, and tones.

One aspect of the phenomena at issue here is patently obvious from the outset - digital technology acts a synthetic substitute for natural perceptual and cognitive processes; These processes should be understood in their deepest sense - ones which allow us to relate to the World Content in every waking and dreaming moment of our lives, and to make sense of the manifold phenomena which confront us. To perceive what happens when these processes are substituted out by digital media technology, we first need a basic understanding of what these processes do for us. We will approach this topic by way of a few phenomenological and aesthetic considerations. First, let us examine why it is that we perceive anything in the world around us. What functions are the "perceptions" in the phenomenal world actually serving in our experience? To stimulate our Imagination here, and to give readers an opportunity to discern some clues to this 'mystery' of perception, I am going to quote a few modern thinkers over a range of time who spoke directly to this function of perceptual phenomena that we are searching for. No matter how abstract the language becomes, remember that these thinkers below were speaking of our immanent phenomenal experience.




Image




Light and colours, heat and cold, extension and figures—in a word the things we see and feel — what are they but so many sensations, notions, ideas, or impressions on the sense? and is it possible to separate, even in thought, any of these from perception?... my conceiving or imagining power does not extend beyond the possibility of real existence or perception... as it is impossible for me to see or feel anything without an actual sensation of that thing, so is it impossible for me to conceive in my thoughts any sensible thing or object distinct from the sensation or perception of it.

- George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710)


Only within a one is [a perception] a property; and only in relation to other properties is it specific... isolated property is basically just a form of sensuous being since it... is now reduced to mere meaning, having, in other words, altogether ceased perceiving and involuted into itself... But sensuous being and meaning mutate into perception.

- Hegel, The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807)


You must, when contemplating nature,
Attend to this, in each and every feature:
There’s nought outside and nought within,
For she is inside out and outside in.
Thus will you grasp, with no delay,
The holy secret, clear as day.

- Goethe, Epirrhema (1819)


The ruin or the blank, that we see when we look at nature, is in our own eye. The axis of vision is not coincident with the axis of things, and so they appear not transparent but opaque. The reason why the world lacks unity, and lies broken and in heaps, is, because man is disunited with himself. He cannot be a naturalist, until he satisfies all the demands of the spirit. Love is as much its demand, as perception. Indeed, neither can be perfect without the other. In the uttermost meaning of the words, thought is devout, and devotion is thought. Deep calls unto deep.

- Emerson, Nature (1836)


The insufficiency of our faculties of perception — an insufficiency verified by our faculties of conception and reasoning — is what has given birth to philosophy. The history of doctrines attests it... No matter how abstract a conception may be it always has its starting point in a perception.

- Bergson, The Creative Mind (1956)


For these thinkers above, the key to understanding the function of perceptions in our phenomenal experience is not what we find in the properties of the perceptual structure, but what we find missing. Take a look at the objects in your room right now. What you will not find, under any circumstances, is an isolated perceptual structure which does not present itself in the context of many other perceptual structures. The lamp does not present itself apart from the table or floor it is resting on. The door does not present itself apart from the walls it is situated between, and the computer monitor does not present itself apart from the wires through which electrical currents pass in order to make the display possible. What is the reason for this fact? As Hegel remarked above, a truly isolated property would be "reduced to mere meaning" and "involute into itself". Put more simply, the perceptual property would disappear, i.e. we would no longer perceive it with any outer quantitative structure. As long as a perceptual structure remains connected to other perceptual structures, and those structures to yet more structures, so on and so forth, the property we can isolate only in our thought is still serving a function in our experience, and it is this function which explains its continued perceptual existence.

So what is this function? It is found within the complement of all perceptual structures, which are their conceptual meanings. Perceptions are like voids of meaning; they are negative images which invite us to fill their voids with our meaningful concepts. This negative image relates to Berkeley's quote above - if we are thinking about a "sensible thing", then we are perceiving it with our thought, and, if we are perceiving it with our thought, that means we have not yet exhausted that perception with our conceptual meaning. Therefore, there cannot possibly exist a thought about some-thing which we have never perceived. Such thinking would be perfectly united with its object and there would be no perception of the object as a distinct entity. Goethe points to this "holy secret" of Nature as well, because "each and every feature" she carries in her perceptions serve as a 'suction' on our conceptual cognition - what appears as an outer 'thing' in our perception is, in essence, an absence of inner conceptual meaning. She offers her appearances as "inside out and outside in" by presenting what is truly absent (meaning) as a perceptual structure. Nature, by presenting her appearances in this manner, invites (or demands) our thoughts to render her subtle meanings increasingly more transparent than opaque. Consider this imaginative visual analogy of the process provided to me by a like-minded soul:


Cleric wrote:Let us imagine ourselves in a 'God' state. We think the thought 'circle' and our cognition assumes the "shape" of the meaning of 'circle'. Our whole reality then consists of the meaning of 'circle': there would be no need for any thought-perception of it, because we experience the complete meaning of it - our cognition is one and the same with the idea, i.e. the meaningful quality of 'circle-ness' through and through. There is nothing that a perception could add to the idea that we now experience as the entire meaning of our Divinity. In fact, if we have a perception in our Divine mind, then this means that there is at least one more idea present - the idea of 'perception'. In the first state, our whole Universe was 'made' of the meaning of 'circle'. Now, in addition to that, we experience also the idea of 'reflection', something which we have thrust out of ourselves in order to symbolize in perception the meaning of 'circle' which was previously our complete reality.

We then 'exhale' out our own cognitive essence and create a void shaped as circle. If we fill it completely with our perfect cognitive essence, then everything becomes the invisible inner meaning of 'circle' again. But we don't allow this to happen. We resist the suction and we keep the void open. Now this void exists for our Divine being. We can now experience many other ideas in relation to it. The void tries to suck in from our meaningful essence an infinity of possible ideas that can try to approximate its shape (every idea except 'circle', which would close the void perfectly). For example, we can try to fill the void with a meaningful concept in the shape of a 'hexagon'. It is like we are saying: "this thing looks to me like a hexagon." The void draws in our cognitive essence into itself and we assume the meaning-shape of a hexagon. Yet, the perception does not completely disappear because the idea that we experience is not a perfect fit. The hexagon fills the circle but there are six sectors of the circle that remain:


Image




Those six sections which remain in the circle image above (light green) correspond to perceptions which persist in the world around us. Take a moment to remember here that the purpose of this phenomenological approach is to indicate how perceptions manifest in our immanent experience. We are not interested in assuming anything about the "fundamental essence" of perceptions or generalizing our immanent experience into any abstract "universal principle" which governs the entire Cosmos. There is no good fruit to be produced from any such purely abstract endeavor, which, as Bergson put it, attempts to "leap in one bound to the eternal". For now, we only need to ask ourselves - when we look at the world around us, assuming we are looking with genuine attention and interest, do the perceptions in our surrounding enviroment invite us, or even compel us, to fill their voids with our meaningful concepts as illustrated above? I do not think this fact is reasonably doubted by anyone engaging in this exercise with good will. We can remember here Bergson's observation that insufficient perception, revealed as such by our conceptual reasoning, has given birth to all philosophy (and, in fact, all knowing inquiries in human history). The next step of our phenomenological endeavior is to confirm the reasoning above with specific perceptual phenomena in our experience.

For instance, let's consider the letters and words we use when speaking and writing, which are those same ever-evolving letters and words which Barfield used to sketch an entire historical account of Western culture. These are the letters and words which I have written previously and which you are reading right this moment. So the perceptions, in this case, are the letters which make up the words, the words which make up sentences, the sentences which make up paragraphs, and so forth. What actually occurs when these perceptions present themselves to our eyes, in the case of reading? We perceive the outer structure of those words, sentences, paragraphs, etc. - which we call their "syntax" - and that syntax stimulates our thought to go searching for the inner conceptual meaning which makes sense of that syntactical structure - which we call their "semantics". No words have semantic meaning in isolation, but rather that meaning lives in the empty spaces between the letters, words and sentences (the latter spaces are indicated by what we call "punctuation"). Consider the following sentence in three formulations to discern carefully how your own cognitive activity responds when perceiving them:


(1) "hereliesthewhitemousewhowaseatenbythebrowncat".


(2) "hereli esthewhitemo usewhowaseate nbytheb rowncat".


(3) "herelies thewhitemouse, whowas eatenbythe browncat".



What else have I done in formulations #2 and #3 above apart from creating and enlarging (or modifying with punctuation) empty spaces within the syntax of the letters and words for your conceptual meanings to fill more easily? Nothing else has been done besides that. Note how the empty spaces do not automatically bring meaning to the structure, but only reveal it after our cognitive activity has been invited in to assume its 'shape' and we accept the invitation with meaningful engagement. The same exact logic used above will also apply to all other perceptual phenomena in our experience. Consider music when we are listening, singing, or dancing to it and discerning its underlying rhythm. This rhythm is discerned, usually subconsciously, by the silent spaces ("intervals") between the beats, notes, and chords. The musical aesthetic also allows us to broaden our phenomenology a bit more to begin considering how our perceptions do not only include physical structures, but also temporal ones. The temporal structures are easily missed when considering simple shapes, objects in our rooms, or words in an essay, but not so much when considering our auditory perception of music, if we are genuinely listening for them. The term "liminal space" was developed to refer to that duration of transition between one state of being and the next state, and in music these spaces are exemplified by "rhythmic thresholds".




Image





Psychologists who have studied these rhythmic thresholds have identified the lowest possible limit that the mind can perceive, with normal waking cognition, as 33 beats per minute ("lower perceptual limit"). They also identified approximately 240 beats per minute as the "upper perceptual limit", which is not the fastest speed at which music can be played, but the threshold at which our normal cognition will fail to notice any significant difference in the musical structure if it were to become any faster. It is very important to remember that these thresholds are limits of our own normal cognitive perception at any given time, rather than absolute limits on the liminal spacing of perception. Above we have already reasoned that these 'spaces' between perceptions (musical beats/notes) seem to invite more conceptual activity the larger they become, but is that the only factor at play? In seeking this answer, we are asking what our immanent experience discloses to us when listening to music at various speeds within these perceptual limits. To be clear, I am not claiming the following is an exact mathematical science. It may not even be a great representation of the perceptual semantics we are exploring. However, with normal waking cognition, and within the narrow boundaries of a written essay, it is likely the best that I can do. We will proceed with the phenomenology of temporal perception by listening to the following musical clips in three stages.


(1) Lower perceptual limit (33 BPM):








(2) Above-Mean Perceptual Limit (180 BPM)








(3) [Almost] Upper Perceptual Limit (240 BPM - Drums)






How did these three clips rate on a spectrum of inviting liminal spaces for your cognition to fill their voids with conceptual meaning? For me, clip #1 was a struggle due to the really prolonged temporal gaps. Yet, after about 10-20 seconds, I could feel my cognitive activity picking up and searching for meaning to imbue within the liminal spaces. Clip #3 was the most difficult for my cognitive activity, as the drum beats came in fast and furious, leaving almost no room for my activity to be welcomed into the song's abode. Clip #2 was the most welcoming by far for me, and, although there was some struggle for the first few bars, it quickly invited my cognitive activity into its natural progression of deep aesthetic meaning and made it feel very welcome. At this point, some readers may be wondering whether their cognitive preferences were mostly an artifact of the song choices, i.e. a result of the fact that most people will prefer Vivaldi's Four Seasons more than an unknown slow-motion Moon song and a death metal hyper-speed drum performance. I don't deny such factors are relevant, but the real question is, are these other preferential factors also reflections of the liminal spacing between the musical perceptions? Reason tells me that our preferences for songs will have a lot to do with how much cognitive 'suction' their liminal spacing stimulates within us.

Much more can be said about the dynamics occurring in these liminal spaces of perceptual phenomena, but now we need to begin returning to the main phenomena at issue in this essay series - mechanism. How many readers would be more willing to apply the adjective "mechanistic" to Clip #3 than they would for the other clips? With that clear connection between the over-narrowing of liminal spacing and meaning, we begin to see what mechanization really takes away from our cognition and perception of the world phenomena we are always encountering around us. It is not only the overall meaning available to any given population which is sacrificed in the ever-increasingly mechanized world, but also the capacity for each individual to play a decisive role in co-creating that meaning through an ever-evolving courtship with Nature; the capacity to microcosmically build up our legacy by giving birth to meaning which will serve as the stable foundations of knowledge for our descendants in centuries to come. In the next part of this essay, we will look more closely and precisely at this phenomena of mechanization in the digital age.

Before we get to this next part, though, it is important to consider that a genuine phenomenology does not arbitrarily end once it diagnoses a deep problem in our experience. This pessimistic and cynical approach to phenomenal inquiry in recent decades is itself an expression of mechanism - it is the computer program terminating once it completes a few basic iterations of its code. The genuine inquiry, instead, seeks to evolve with its phenomena as the nerve-senses evolve within a living organism and continually feed back meaningful information to the brain; it seeks to become increasingly united in meaning with the phenomena and therefore anticipate how its future stages will blossom in our experience. To employ a photographic analogy, the genuine phenomenology seeks to focus its lens vertically and deeply on its subject, rather than only widely and horizontally. Our thoughts must be transfigured into seeds planted deeply within the perceptual soil, rather than scattered loosely over the ground. We must remember to go deep into the phenomena, not wide. Going deep with our cognitive activity is the essence of life and novelty, while going wide inevitably becomes repetitive, mechanistic, and, therefore, the enemy of life.

"As the discoveries of Kepler and Galileo slowly filtered through to the popular consciousness, first of all simple words like atmosphere, down, earth, planet, sky, space, sphere, star, up,… underwent a profound yet subtle semantic change... If we cared to examine them closely enough, we should probably find that from this point a certain change of meaning gradually spread over all words containing the notion of attraction, or ideas closely related to it. The twin phenomena of gravitation and magnetism, contemplated by most of us at an early age, and impalpably present in the meanings of so many of the words we hear spoken around us, make the conception of one lifeless body acting on another from a distance seem easy and familiar."
- Owen Barfield, History in English Words (1953)
"Most people would sooner regard themselves as a piece of lava in the moon than as an 'I'"
findingblanks
Posts: 670
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 12:36 am

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by findingblanks »

Bravo on all the time, effort and vigorous thought that went into this fascinating essay!
coexistence
Posts: 22
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 4:56 am
Location: India
Contact:

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by coexistence »

Hi,
Great article.
Let us understand what came first reality or language and words in the language.
I am sure everyone knows that reality was there first.

Coexistence as a reality of the form and the formless expressed itself slowly as evolution progressed.
In the material world there was just noise and sound.
In the living world of plants teh sound became systematic and was connected to the activity happening.
In the animal world the sound had specific connotations and was conveying messages to each other.
The internal feelings and the situations needed for existence took various forms in different species.
All these special sounds helped them find mates,procreate,find food ,take flight and keep themselves safe.
They also had sounds to express joy.
In the cognisant world of homo sapiens the language was formed to help each other comprehend and understand reality.
All the languages in all cultures help express the existential reality and the purpose is only to help the other person see the reality with his virtual eyes
and experience the same.

I am not a good writer but can explain the whole concept and answer any question on a 1 to 1 session if anyone is interested.
User avatar
AshvinP
Posts: 5457
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 5:00 am
Location: USA

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by AshvinP »

findingblanks wrote: Fri Oct 22, 2021 1:14 am Bravo on all the time, effort and vigorous thought that went into this fascinating essay!

FB - thank you, especially for reading it!

I know we have been at each other's throats, so to speak, since the Steiner-Schop thread. It's safe to say I grew very frustrated with your approach and you with mine. But, in the spirit of one of my favorite recent singers, Adele, I say we call it:





(for now)
"Most people would sooner regard themselves as a piece of lava in the moon than as an 'I'"
User avatar
AshvinP
Posts: 5457
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 5:00 am
Location: USA

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by AshvinP »

coexistence wrote: Fri Oct 22, 2021 3:01 am Hi,
Great article.
Let us understand what came first reality or language and words in the language.
I am sure everyone knows that reality was there first.

Coexistence as a reality of the form and the formless expressed itself slowly as evolution progressed.
In the material world there was just noise and sound.
In the living world of plants teh sound became systematic and was connected to the activity happening.
In the animal world the sound had specific connotations and was conveying messages to each other.
The internal feelings and the situations needed for existence took various forms in different species.
All these special sounds helped them find mates,procreate,find food ,take flight and keep themselves safe.
They also had sounds to express joy.
In the cognisant world of homo sapiens the language was formed to help each other comprehend and understand reality.
All the languages in all cultures help express the existential reality and the purpose is only to help the other person see the reality with his virtual eyes
and experience the same.

I am not a good writer but can explain the whole concept and answer any question on a 1 to 1 session if anyone is interested.

Thanks, Anand!

If we mean "reality" as in currently sense-perceptible reality, I would say that reality and language co-arose together. That is also Barfield's thesis. It is true, though, that primal tones first permeated sense-perceptible reality. The general thrust of the essay is that the perceptual phenomena of the world can instruct us about all of these spiritual evolutionary progressions in detail, through our own ideational activity, IF it is not overly-materialized (or overly-spiritualized) through digital mechanistic technology, which, going by recent developments, it is safe to say our normal intellectual perception-cognition is already overly-mechanized and needs major correctives soon.
"Most people would sooner regard themselves as a piece of lava in the moon than as an 'I'"
User avatar
Cleric K
Posts: 1653
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 9:40 pm

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by Cleric K »

Brilliant all round! Thank you, Ashvin! The "laminal space" concept is very useful and very well illustrated in your examples!

Keep them rolling!
findingblanks
Posts: 670
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 12:36 am

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by findingblanks »

"FB - thank you, especially for reading it! I know we have been at each other's throats, so to speak, since the Steiner-Schop thread. It's safe to say I grew very frustrated with your approach and you with mine. But, in the spirit of one of my favorite recent singers, Adele, I say we call it..."

What a wonderful comment and video to start the day with :) Water under the bridge indeed. Here's to what I hope will be a fascinating and fruitful conversation on your thoughtful essay. Yes, I'm so happy to start from a blank slate and extract any and all shadowy-dancy assumptions I've been bringing carrying. If I am quiet in this particular thread, it is just that I want to get my bearings and think specifically about your particular perspective (as I grasp it) before I respond; so that I can respond in a way that actually communicates the respect I have for you and the thoughts. Great work.
ParadoxZone
Posts: 78
Joined: Fri Jul 23, 2021 7:59 pm

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by ParadoxZone »

Hi Ashvin,

Captivating as ever, thanks.

As regards language and it's origins, I was interested to see this today from Taleb:



He's been at this for a long time as an amateur philologist.
User avatar
AshvinP
Posts: 5457
Joined: Thu Jan 14, 2021 5:00 am
Location: USA

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by AshvinP »

Cleric wrote:Brilliant all round! Thank you, Ashvin! The "laminal space" concept is very useful and very well illustrated in your examples!

Keep them rolling!
ParadoxZone wrote: Fri Oct 22, 2021 9:15 pm Hi Ashvin,

Captivating as ever, thanks.

Thanks, Cleric and PZ! I just came across "liminal space" when researching perceptual limits of music. My original sub-title was "The Semantics of Perception", but then I found that term and decided to be one of the cool kids 8-)

PZ wrote:As regards language and it's origins, I was interested to see this today from Taleb:



He's been at this for a long time as an amateur philologist.

Nice. It is really an amazing inspiration when one makes the connection between sense-perceptible 'truths' of phenomenal relations and moral imaginations which precipitate from the spiritual realms. As Emerson put it, "Every word which is used to express a moral or intellectual fact, if traced to its root, is found to be borrowed from some material appearance." But, alas, this isn't a one-way street... and a certain sense-perceptible world can come to resemble a certain void of moral imaginations as well. That is a key issue I will focus on in the next part. Barfield points to this concerning development in StA:

Barfield wrote:Imagination is not, as some poets have thought, simply synonymous with good. It may be either good or evil. As long as art remained primarily mimetic, the evil which imagination could do was limited by nature. Again, as long as it was treated as an amusement, the evil which it could do was limited in scope. But in an age when the connection between imagination and figuration is beginning to be dimly realized, when the fact of the directionally creator relation is beginning to break through into consciousness, both the good and the evil latent in the working of imagination begin to appear unlimited. We have seen in the Romantic movement an instance of the way in which the making of images may react upon the collective representations. It is a fairly rudimentary instance, but even so it has already gone beyond the dreams and responses of a leisured few. The economic and social structure of Switzerland is noticeably affected by its tourist industry, and that is due only in part to increased facilities of travel. It is due not less to the condition that (whatever may be said about their ‘particles’) the mountains which twentieth-century man sees are not the mountains which eighteenth-century man saw.

It may be objected that this is a very small matter, and that it will be a long time before the imagination of man substantially alters those appearances of nature with which his figuration supplies him. But then I am taking the long view. Even so, we need not be too confident. Even if the pace of change remained the same, one who is really sensitive to (for example) the difference between the medieval collective representations and our own will be aware that, without traveling any greater distance than we have come since the fourteenth century, we could very well move forward into a chaotically empty or fantastically hideous world. But the pace of change has not remained the same. It has accelerated and is accelerating.

We should remember this, when appraising the aberrations of the formally representational arts. Of course, in so far as these are due to affectation, they are of no importance. But in so far as they are genuine, they are genuine because the artist has in some way or other experienced the world he represents. And in so far as they are appreciated, they are appreciated by those who are themselves willing to make a move towards seeing the world in that way, and, ultimately therefore, seeing that kind of world. We should remember this, when we see pictures of a dog with six legs emerging from a vegetable marrow or a woman with a motorbicycle substituted for her left breast
"Most people would sooner regard themselves as a piece of lava in the moon than as an 'I'"
User avatar
Federica
Posts: 1709
Joined: Sat May 14, 2022 2:30 pm
Location: Sweden

Re: (Essay) A Phenomenology of Mechanism: The Liminal Spaces of Perception

Post by Federica »

AshvinP wrote: Thu Oct 21, 2021 9:46 pm
Image



“We must not forget that nine-tenths of the words comprising the vocabulary of a civilised nation are never used by more than at most one tenth of the population; while of the remaining tithe, nine-tenths of those who use them are commonly aware of about one-tenth of their meanings.”
- Owen Barfield, History in English Words (1953)


Owen Barfield wrote a history of Western culture by doing nothing apart from following the origins and transformations of English words. In this endeavor, Barfield approached history in a very unique way. He perceived how the presence, absence, and use of various words, in relation to that of other words, could provide clear knowledge of Western civilization to someone otherwise ignorant of it. Not only that, but it could provide us a more objectively valid, living, and qualitative knowledge of this evolving history than all of the prosaic accounts taught by professors to students in universities. Barfield remarked, "It has only just begun to dawn on us that in our own language alone, not to speak of its many companions, the past history of humanity is spread out in an imperishable map, just as the history of the mineral earth lies embedded in the layers of its outer crust. But there is this difference between the record of the rocks and the secrets which are hidden in language: whereas the former can only give us a knowledge of outward, dead things—such as forgotten seas and the bodily shapes of prehistoric animals and primitive men—language has preserved for us the inner, living history of man's soul. It reveals the evolution of consciousness."

It is true that language provides an imperishable map of inner experience, but that is even more true of the sensible perceptions in the world which all language is drawn from. Barfield, and one of his favorite poets, Ralph Waldo Emerson, pointed attention often to the fact that all language we currently use to symbolize inner mental states and dispositions began as words reflecting the perceptible appearances of the world. Emerson observed, "Right originally means straight; wrong means twisted. Spirit primarily means wind; transgression, the crossing of a line; supercilious, the raising of the eye-brow." This ideal quality of physical images has not disappeared, but has only been veiled by our own abstract and limited cognition. One major obstacle to examining the transformations of perceptions, as opposed to words, is that most people cannot access perceptions beyond a very limited range of their recent memory. There is another approach, however, which can still yield fruit. We can start with our current perceptual experiences and see what those disclose to us about the phenomena in question, which, in this case, is the mechanisms of modern human culture and daily life. To begin with what presents itself to our experience most immediately is the genuinely phenomenological approach.



“All conscious nature has experiences of pleasure and pain. Man alone can deliberately will the repetition of an experience. And repetition, experienced as such, is at the heart, for good and evil, of his faculty of reasoning, and thus makes possible his language, his art, his morality, and indeed his humanity. Yet it is the enemy of life, for repetition is itself the principle, not of life but of mechanism.”
-Owen Barfield, Orpheus: A Poetic Drama



The willing of repetitive experience is also what we call Thinking and Memory. That is why Barfield places it at the very foundation of so many qualities which make us uniquely human. How can such qualities, which ground our speech, our reasoning intellect, our art, and our morality, then transform into "the enemy of life"? A famous philosopher once said, "evil is truth which is out of season". Many riddles surrounding the current state of humanity in the modern age can be understood through the lens of this simple Wisdom. Specifically, for our purposes here, the enemy of life arrives when this unique human quality of repetitive experiencing, which underlies all technological development in the modern age, is clinged to for the conveniences and comforts it provides long past their 'expiration date'. This stubborn refusal to evolve with the currents of cognition - this deeply ingrained desire to constantly swim upstream against them - then compounds itself into something which carries much more tragic consequences for humanity as a whole, the longer it is ignored and festers within us. We will see how those consequences have already unfolded in modern society and are still unfolding around us in due course. First, Barfield takes us back to the Reinassance era, when many of the predecessors to our current English vocabulary were reintroduced into the streams of Western thought.


Barfield wrote:The new intercourse with the ancient literatures of Greece and Rome naturally brought into English a positive stream of ‘literary borrowings’. At first these were mostly Latin words. If we try to imagine an English from which such words as accommodate, capable, capacious, compute, corroborate, distinguish, efficacy, estimate, experiment, insinuate, investigate, and a host of others equally common are as yet absent, we may partly realize what an important part was played by the Renaissance in producing the language in which we speak and think.


At this very early stage, there was still a feeling for the concrete experiences to which these words referred. At the end of the 17th century, a "computer" was still a human being "who calculates... whose occupation is to make arithmetical calculations". By the end of the 19th century, we first get its usage as a "calculating machine" with its own existence independent of any particular human being. It is only in 1937, through the personality of Alan Turing, that the word is first used in its modern sense of "programmable digital electronic device for performing mathematical or logical operations". One should clearly sense the distancing that is occurring here from the human body-brain and its living cognitive processes. The philosophical meaning of "abstract" as a verb from the mid-16th century is, "to draw away, withdraw, remove".  Let us be clear - for human thinking to draw away from nature and its processes was absolutely necessary for any modern technology to develop, such as that which I am taking advantage of now. We only fool ourselves if we imagine that we could have done without the Wisdom of this process. Yet our clear thinking should remain equally clear as we explore, in precise and concrete terms, what qualities of living experience we have also forsaken in this abstracting process of the modern mechanical age.

Mechanical technology itself is not unique to the modern age. What is unique is how this technology has influenced every dimension of our cultural existence, right down to the way we perceive and think about the world around us. It is not only our ideas about the world which have taken on a mechanical nature, but our method of forming ideas has been mechanized. That is what Barfield refers to above as "consciousness"; the generally subconscious way in which we perceive and cognize the World Content. Our considerations here will be supplemented by some of Barfield's findings along the way, but we will focus mostly on the digital age of technology which has only come into widespread use over the last few decades after Barfield's passing. Since the dawn of the 21st century, this technology has come to govern every sphere of our lives from our mornings to our evenings, our weekdays to our weekends, and our youth to our adulthood. It dictates our decisions in our homes and offices, in our cities and countrysides, and in our social, civic, personal, and professional lives. Based on his writings and the spirit of his thought more generally, it is a safe bet that Barfield would be very concerned with the accelerating pace of this development.

Many modern psychology books, articles, YouTube channels, and podcasts have tried to explore the harmful effects of digital technology. These analyses of the situtation paint with very broad strokes, thereby remaining hoplessly abstract and mostly unhelpful. The mechanization phenomena is treated as one more in a long list of bad habits, like smoking or eating fast food. It is referred to as yet another activity that people in the modern world should either avoid altogether or use in moderation to whatever extent possible. These approaches cannot possibly be helpful because they fail to diagnose the problem we are dealing with in its living essence. The task of any genuine "phenomenology" is to observe and deeply contemplate how these underlying living dynamics of the phenomena manifest in our immanent experience. We start with the phenomenal appearances - in this case, various aspects of digital technology - but we don't arbitarily end with the mere appearances if we can go further and deeper through sound logical reasoning. It is by penetrating into the depths of phenomena that we begin to actually hear their tales and tunes, otherwise muted, at first only by faint whispers, but later through resounding words, images, and tones.

One aspect of the phenomena at issue here is patently obvious from the outset - digital technology acts a synthetic substitute for natural perceptual and cognitive processes; These processes should be understood in their deepest sense - ones which allow us to relate to the World Content in every waking and dreaming moment of our lives, and to make sense of the manifold phenomena which confront us. To perceive what happens when these processes are substituted out by digital media technology, we first need a basic understanding of what these processes do for us. We will approach this topic by way of a few phenomenological and aesthetic considerations. First, let us examine why it is that we perceive anything in the world around us. What functions are the "perceptions" in the phenomenal world actually serving in our experience? To stimulate our Imagination here, and to give readers an opportunity to discern some clues to this 'mystery' of perception, I am going to quote a few modern thinkers over a range of time who spoke directly to this function of perceptual phenomena that we are searching for. No matter how abstract the language becomes, remember that these thinkers below were speaking of our immanent phenomenal experience.




Image




Light and colours, heat and cold, extension and figures—in a word the things we see and feel — what are they but so many sensations, notions, ideas, or impressions on the sense? and is it possible to separate, even in thought, any of these from perception?... my conceiving or imagining power does not extend beyond the possibility of real existence or perception... as it is impossible for me to see or feel anything without an actual sensation of that thing, so is it impossible for me to conceive in my thoughts any sensible thing or object distinct from the sensation or perception of it.

- George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710)


Only within a one is [a perception] a property; and only in relation to other properties is it specific... isolated property is basically just a form of sensuous being since it... is now reduced to mere meaning, having, in other words, altogether ceased perceiving and involuted into itself... But sensuous being and meaning mutate into perception.

- Hegel, The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807)


You must, when contemplating nature,
Attend to this, in each and every feature:
There’s nought outside and nought within,
For she is inside out and outside in.
Thus will you grasp, with no delay,
The holy secret, clear as day.

- Goethe, Epirrhema (1819)


The ruin or the blank, that we see when we look at nature, is in our own eye. The axis of vision is not coincident with the axis of things, and so they appear not transparent but opaque. The reason why the world lacks unity, and lies broken and in heaps, is, because man is disunited with himself. He cannot be a naturalist, until he satisfies all the demands of the spirit. Love is as much its demand, as perception. Indeed, neither can be perfect without the other. In the uttermost meaning of the words, thought is devout, and devotion is thought. Deep calls unto deep.

- Emerson, Nature (1836)


The insufficiency of our faculties of perception — an insufficiency verified by our faculties of conception and reasoning — is what has given birth to philosophy. The history of doctrines attests it... No matter how abstract a conception may be it always has its starting point in a perception.

- Bergson, The Creative Mind (1956)


For these thinkers above, the key to understanding the function of perceptions in our phenomenal experience is not what we find in the properties of the perceptual structure, but what we find missing. Take a look at the objects in your room right now. What you will not find, under any circumstances, is an isolated perceptual structure which does not present itself in the context of many other perceptual structures. The lamp does not present itself apart from the table or floor it is resting on. The door does not present itself apart from the walls it is situated between, and the computer monitor does not present itself apart from the wires through which electrical currents pass in order to make the display possible. What is the reason for this fact? As Hegel remarked above, a truly isolated property would be "reduced to mere meaning" and "involute into itself". Put more simply, the perceptual property would disappear, i.e. we would no longer perceive it with any outer quantitative structure. As long as a perceptual structure remains connected to other perceptual structures, and those structures to yet more structures, so on and so forth, the property we can isolate only in our thought is still serving a function in our experience, and it is this function which explains its continued perceptual existence.

So what is this function? It is found within the complement of all perceptual structures, which are their conceptual meanings. Perceptions are like voids of meaning; they are negative images which invite us to fill their voids with our meaningful concepts. This negative image relates to Berkeley's quote above - if we are thinking about a "sensible thing", then we are perceiving it with our thought, and, if we are perceiving it with our thought, that means we have not yet exhausted that perception with our conceptual meaning. Therefore, there cannot possibly exist a thought about some-thing which we have never perceived. Such thinking would be perfectly united with its object and there would be no perception of the object as a distinct entity. Goethe points to this "holy secret" of Nature as well, because "each and every feature" she carries in her perceptions serve as a 'suction' on our conceptual cognition - what appears as an outer 'thing' in our perception is, in essence, an absence of inner conceptual meaning. She offers her appearances as "inside out and outside in" by presenting what is truly absent (meaning) as a perceptual structure. Nature, by presenting her appearances in this manner, invites (or demands) our thoughts to render her subtle meanings increasingly more transparent than opaque. Consider this imaginative visual analogy of the process provided to me by a like-minded soul:


Cleric wrote:Let us imagine ourselves in a 'God' state. We think the thought 'circle' and our cognition assumes the "shape" of the meaning of 'circle'. Our whole reality then consists of the meaning of 'circle': there would be no need for any thought-perception of it, because we experience the complete meaning of it - our cognition is one and the same with the idea, i.e. the meaningful quality of 'circle-ness' through and through. There is nothing that a perception could add to the idea that we now experience as the entire meaning of our Divinity. In fact, if we have a perception in our Divine mind, then this means that there is at least one more idea present - the idea of 'perception'. In the first state, our whole Universe was 'made' of the meaning of 'circle'. Now, in addition to that, we experience also the idea of 'reflection', something which we have thrust out of ourselves in order to symbolize in perception the meaning of 'circle' which was previously our complete reality.

We then 'exhale' out our own cognitive essence and create a void shaped as circle. If we fill it completely with our perfect cognitive essence, then everything becomes the invisible inner meaning of 'circle' again. But we don't allow this to happen. We resist the suction and we keep the void open. Now this void exists for our Divine being. We can now experience many other ideas in relation to it. The void tries to suck in from our meaningful essence an infinity of possible ideas that can try to approximate its shape (every idea except 'circle', which would close the void perfectly). For example, we can try to fill the void with a meaningful concept in the shape of a 'hexagon'. It is like we are saying: "this thing looks to me like a hexagon." The void draws in our cognitive essence into itself and we assume the meaning-shape of a hexagon. Yet, the perception does not completely disappear because the idea that we experience is not a perfect fit. The hexagon fills the circle but there are six sectors of the circle that remain:


Image




Those six sections which remain in the circle image above (light green) correspond to perceptions which persist in the world around us. Take a moment to remember here that the purpose of this phenomenological approach is to indicate how perceptions manifest in our immanent experience. We are not interested in assuming anything about the "fundamental essence" of perceptions or generalizing our immanent experience into any abstract "universal principle" which governs the entire Cosmos. There is no good fruit to be produced from any such purely abstract endeavor, which, as Bergson put it, attempts to "leap in one bound to the eternal". For now, we only need to ask ourselves - when we look at the world around us, assuming we are looking with genuine attention and interest, do the perceptions in our surrounding enviroment invite us, or even compel us, to fill their voids with our meaningful concepts as illustrated above? I do not think this fact is reasonably doubted by anyone engaging in this exercise with good will. We can remember here Bergson's observation that insufficient perception, revealed as such by our conceptual reasoning, has given birth to all philosophy (and, in fact, all knowing inquiries in human history). The next step of our phenomenological endeavior is to confirm the reasoning above with specific perceptual phenomena in our experience.

For instance, let's consider the letters and words we use when speaking and writing, which are those same ever-evolving letters and words which Barfield used to sketch an entire historical account of Western culture. These are the letters and words which I have written previously and which you are reading right this moment. So the perceptions, in this case, are the letters which make up the words, the words which make up sentences, the sentences which make up paragraphs, and so forth. What actually occurs when these perceptions present themselves to our eyes, in the case of reading? We perceive the outer structure of those words, sentences, paragraphs, etc. - which we call their "syntax" - and that syntax stimulates our thought to go searching for the inner conceptual meaning which makes sense of that syntactical structure - which we call their "semantics". No words have semantic meaning in isolation, but rather that meaning lives in the empty spaces between the letters, words and sentences (the latter spaces are indicated by what we call "punctuation"). Consider the following sentence in three formulations to discern carefully how your own cognitive activity responds when perceiving them:


(1) "hereliesthewhitemousewhowaseatenbythebrowncat".


(2) "hereli esthewhitemo usewhowaseate nbytheb rowncat".


(3) "herelies thewhitemouse, whowas eatenbythe browncat".



What else have I done in formulations #2 and #3 above apart from creating and enlarging (or modifying with punctuation) empty spaces within the syntax of the letters and words for your conceptual meanings to fill more easily? Nothing else has been done besides that. Note how the empty spaces do not automatically bring meaning to the structure, but only reveal it after our cognitive activity has been invited in to assume its 'shape' and we accept the invitation with meaningful engagement. The same exact logic used above will also apply to all other perceptual phenomena in our experience. Consider music when we are listening, singing, or dancing to it and discerning its underlying rhythm. This rhythm is discerned, usually subconsciously, by the silent spaces ("intervals") between the beats, notes, and chords. The musical aesthetic also allows us to broaden our phenomenology a bit more to begin considering how our perceptions do not only include physical structures, but also temporal ones. The temporal structures are easily missed when considering simple shapes, objects in our rooms, or words in an essay, but not so much when considering our auditory perception of music, if we are genuinely listening for them. The term "liminal space" was developed to refer to that duration of transition between one state of being and the next state, and in music these spaces are exemplified by "rhythmic thresholds".




Image





Psychologists who have studied these rhythmic thresholds have identified the lowest possible limit that the mind can perceive, with normal waking cognition, as 33 beats per minute ("lower perceptual limit"). They also identified approximately 240 beats per minute as the "upper perceptual limit", which is not the fastest speed at which music can be played, but the threshold at which our normal cognition will fail to notice any significant difference in the musical structure if it were to become any faster. It is very important to remember that these thresholds are limits of our own normal cognitive perception at any given time, rather than absolute limits on the liminal spacing of perception. Above we have already reasoned that these 'spaces' between perceptions (musical beats/notes) seem to invite more conceptual activity the larger they become, but is that the only factor at play? In seeking this answer, we are asking what our immanent experience discloses to us when listening to music at various speeds within these perceptual limits. To be clear, I am not claiming the following is an exact mathematical science. It may not even be a great representation of the perceptual semantics we are exploring. However, with normal waking cognition, and within the narrow boundaries of a written essay, it is likely the best that I can do. We will proceed with the phenomenology of temporal perception by listening to the following musical clips in three stages.


(1) Lower perceptual limit (33 BPM):








(2) Above-Mean Perceptual Limit (180 BPM)








(3) [Almost] Upper Perceptual Limit (240 BPM - Drums)






How did these three clips rate on a spectrum of inviting liminal spaces for your cognition to fill their voids with conceptual meaning? For me, clip #1 was a struggle due to the really prolonged temporal gaps. Yet, after about 10-20 seconds, I could feel my cognitive activity picking up and searching for meaning to imbue within the liminal spaces. Clip #3 was the most difficult for my cognitive activity, as the drum beats came in fast and furious, leaving almost no room for my activity to be welcomed into the song's abode. Clip #2 was the most welcoming by far for me, and, although there was some struggle for the first few bars, it quickly invited my cognitive activity into its natural progression of deep aesthetic meaning and made it feel very welcome. At this point, some readers may be wondering whether their cognitive preferences were mostly an artifact of the song choices, i.e. a result of the fact that most people will prefer Vivaldi's Four Seasons more than an unknown slow-motion Moon song and a death metal hyper-speed drum performance. I don't deny such factors are relevant, but the real question is, are these other preferential factors also reflections of the liminal spacing between the musical perceptions? Reason tells me that our preferences for songs will have a lot to do with how much cognitive 'suction' their liminal spacing stimulates within us.

Much more can be said about the dynamics occurring in these liminal spaces of perceptual phenomena, but now we need to begin returning to the main phenomena at issue in this essay series - mechanism. How many readers would be more willing to apply the adjective "mechanistic" to Clip #3 than they would for the other clips? With that clear connection between the over-narrowing of liminal spacing and meaning, we begin to see what mechanization really takes away from our cognition and perception of the world phenomena we are always encountering around us. It is not only the overall meaning available to any given population which is sacrificed in the ever-increasingly mechanized world, but also the capacity for each individual to play a decisive role in co-creating that meaning through an ever-evolving courtship with Nature; the capacity to microcosmically build up our legacy by giving birth to meaning which will serve as the stable foundations of knowledge for our descendants in centuries to come. In the next part of this essay, we will look more closely and precisely at this phenomena of mechanization in the digital age.

Before we get to this next part, though, it is important to consider that a genuine phenomenology does not arbitrarily end once it diagnoses a deep problem in our experience. This pessimistic and cynical approach to phenomenal inquiry in recent decades is itself an expression of mechanism - it is the computer program terminating once it completes a few basic iterations of its code. The genuine inquiry, instead, seeks to evolve with its phenomena as the nerve-senses evolve within a living organism and continually feed back meaningful information to the brain; it seeks to become increasingly united in meaning with the phenomena and therefore anticipate how its future stages will blossom in our experience. To employ a photographic analogy, the genuine phenomenology seeks to focus its lens vertically and deeply on its subject, rather than only widely and horizontally. Our thoughts must be transfigured into seeds planted deeply within the perceptual soil, rather than scattered loosely over the ground. We must remember to go deep into the phenomena, not wide. Going deep with our cognitive activity is the essence of life and novelty, while going wide inevitably becomes repetitive, mechanistic, and, therefore, the enemy of life.

"As the discoveries of Kepler and Galileo slowly filtered through to the popular consciousness, first of all simple words like atmosphere, down, earth, planet, sky, space, sphere, star, up,… underwent a profound yet subtle semantic change... If we cared to examine them closely enough, we should probably find that from this point a certain change of meaning gradually spread over all words containing the notion of attraction, or ideas closely related to it. The twin phenomena of gravitation and magnetism, contemplated by most of us at an early age, and impalpably present in the meanings of so many of the words we hear spoken around us, make the conception of one lifeless body acting on another from a distance seem easy and familiar."
- Owen Barfield, History in English Words (1953)


Ashvin,

Going through my finished text before posting, I feel I should add a disclaimer, to start with. Much of what follows is in the form of statements rather than questions. I’m expressing my current position with some level of resolution, but I am fully aware that it could evolve, as it has happened here some times already. Please don’t read what follows as confrontational, I just don’t want to conceal my thoughts, because I have put my best efforts and goodwill in them.


Amazing introduction on language! I’d love to stay there for hours but I’m nudging myself to the main topic, it will be a long post already. The start is the ambivalent idea of repetitive experience and its potential to become evil when it’s clung to for the purpose of comfort and convenience. I am very much aligned with this idea, but at the same time I feel that something is missing here, or I am missing something here. The intuition is that it must be true, but maybe in some more specific sense. Because for example in music - taking this example since you later use it - the musical meaning is built on repetitive tempo. I know you then distinguish different speeds in the temporal structure, however it's noticeable that whatever the beats per minute, without consistent and lawful repetition there’s just no music. My spontaneous thought at the first reading was, can the amount of beats per minute really make the difference between mechanistic, repetitive music which is “out of season” thus evil on one side, and good, graceful music on the other? And more generally, because repetition is the necessary backbone of musical experience, do you mean that indulging in the pleasure of writing, playing, or listening to music is an ambivalent, problematic activity in itself, or that some music is evil?
Conversely, is all technological development underlain by repetitive experience? In which sense? How does repetition underlie technology differently than it underlies everything else in the perceptual world?


It seems to me that the overindulging in the convenience of technology, which is a problem indeed, does not come from repetition primarily. I think it comes from estrangement from Nature. By the way, what is it meant by technology - is the wheel to be considered a technological development? If not, why not? Beyond the digital tech focus of the essay, do you consider all the developments that came with the first industrial revolution problematic, or maybe only the ones that came more recently, with automation and information technology? Where do you put the threshold?
I would argue that if we look at estrangement from Nature - rather than repetition - as the principle that leads to, or can lead to, excessive convenience and comfort, we can see how it holds true across all the technological temporal spectrum in its broadest sense. The wheel is an elementary means of estrangement from Nature, just as, say, the printing press is, or electricity to a wider extent, or telephone, or, to a major and growing extent, digital technology.
I should clarify here that I personally don’t have any negative orientation to digital technology. I know it’s here to stay and that it’s not to be eliminated, and I am actually immensely grateful for digital technology. I am every day of the week well aware that without digital technology I simply wouldn’t have had access to the vast majority of the knowledge and information I have been able to access. I couldn’t be on this forum without it. I couldn’t do my (main) job without it. I couldn’t communicate with others across space the way I do. I couldn’t have explored and learned even the tenth of what I have been lucky to explore and discover and learn, without digital technology. This being said, I do agree with you and see the risks of a biased orientation towards technology.

It is only in 1937, through the personality of Alan Turing, that the word [computer] is first used in its modern sense of "programmable digital electronic device for performing mathematical or logical operations". One should clearly sense the distancing that is occurring here from the human body-brain and its living cognitive processes.

As I see it, what one should rather sense here is the distancing occurring from the human living cognitive process and Nature, the perceptual world, where we can include the body, and even the brain. It’s an estrangement from Nature. I don’t see how else you intended the body-brain to come in here, and especially the brain? Or maybe you intended it in that same way, and then we agree. As a drawing away from Nature, yes, it is an abstraction, and I find it insightful to inquire “what qualities of living experience we have also forsaken in this abstracting process”, but then you qualify the abstracting process as pertaining to “the modern mechanical age” and here I am not sure. Abstraction seems to me an overarching, maybe the most overarching human trend or process of all, that started way before the “modern mechanical age”. Ancient Greek already has plethora of abstract words!


What I find brilliant and new to me in your exposure is the uncovering of this correlation between abstraction and technology. Your reasoning makes me also realize that it’s been, and it’s being, a drawing away from Nature just as well as a drawing away from ourselves and our livingly experienced cognition. As we over-objectify Nature through abstracting it into transparent concepts, we move in parallel with regard to our “I”. The focus increasingly goes to a glorified object as unsaturated concept, whilst both Nature and the “I” go out of focus, are extracted from the process and parked at Vantage point. Nature and the “I” - or rather the precursor of the “I” - started off in direct connection with each other, but then gradually, the I became the full-fledged I, and with that birth - fully completed at the Plato-Aristotle cross - a tween element arose: Abstraction (let me capitalize it) which has grown into an intermediary link between the thinking I and Nature. Further, Abstraction has become more and more central in this mediated tripartite relation Nature-Abstraction-I, or the mother and her two tween offsprings. And now Abstraction has taken the exact central position in cognition, it’s being the dominant tween in the center, so it is currently eclipsing the light of Nature for the I. I am reminded of another way to say it, from another essay here: thinking is being predominantly engulfed by object, intended here as an epochal trend, rather than as a transient mode of individual thinking. By necessity, the thinking "I" still connects concepts and percepts to create experience, but because it’s not being vigilant on what it's doing, it forgets to press ‘refresh experience’ and lets the resulting mental images dry out, die out, and like helium balloons reach the Abstraction hall of fame.


In this perspective, technology, in its largest sense, seems to be the manifest, tangible face of transparent Abstraction, its control light, its visible suit. What I remain doubtful about is the specific pointing to mechanical, or repetitive technology of the modern age. I don’t see that any tipping point has happened in our cognition as a function of the mechanical-repetitive qualities and the pervasiveness of technology. As I see it, there’s been no real tipping point yet. Instead it’s been a progressive, smooth movement towards more abstraction and more technology. If I had to hazard a future look, I would imagine that the real tipping point is ahead, and will consist not in eliminating or minimizing technology, but in starting dephasing Abstraction, whereof technology is only the suit, changing the articulation of the tripartite axis Nature-Abstraction-I, dislocating it, moving our tween element on the side, giving our stuck thinking habits a bit of a hysteretic shake, so that we can discover the light of Nature again, while being a fully separate I-entity this time. This move also equals moving cognition out of parking lot Vantage, which is sort of our tween’s artificial I, or the core, the attracting heart of Abstraction. So when I read
It is not only our ideas about the world which have taken on a mechanical nature, but our method of forming ideas has been mechanized [in relation to digital media technology]
I think: Yes! But I would prefer to replace ‘mechanical’ with ‘abstract’. I will hopefully clarify this further by means of following your deep dive into “what natural perceptual-cognitive processes do for us” as a way to consider what happens to our perception-cognition when we substitute digital technology for these natural processes.


Here I’m following the idea that the perceptual world is a playground for thinking, where we are invited, or compelled to, jump in with concepts and ideas to try and fit the percepts, so that meaningful experience can arise. Percepts suck in concepts, and as they match, or intersect, knowledge is generated. To illustrate this function of natural perceptions, you take written language as a first example. Here I immediately wonder, why did you choose a double-layered perception such as language as an example, rather than start simple, maybe with a sensory perception? Let me explain. Within your example, there is the case of the perceiver who does not know the alphabet. This perceiver also perceives the interspaces in sentences 2 and 3, and certainly still makes sense of these percepts by matching the perceived graphical forms with concepts, let’s say esthetical concepts. So the suction does operate, although it is very different from the one a literate person would experience. But ok, let’s stay with this literate person now. I find the example in this case confusing in many ways. First, the spaces have meaning as a graphical, visual element, which, yes, facilitates the reading experience, as a convenience, however spacing has no impact on the plane of decoding the symbols and assigning meaning to them, which is what the example was pointing to in the first place. So I would accept the spaces, in the sense they are proposed in the example, only for the illiterate perceiver, who has to remain on the bare visual experiential plane. For the literate one, the process of assigning meaning to the sentence is completely distinct from the process of reading the sentence! It’s a second layer that starts only after the first layer, the visual one, is made possible, no matter how uncomfortable and entangled, or easy and fluid, we make this first layer for the reader. For the illiterate, the example works well, because there is only one process, the visual one, and it’s not a reading process, there is no alphabet-word-syntax decoding here. There is only the evaluation of a form, as one would do with a painting, and spaces then do enter the meaning-making process directly. On the same logic, I don’t understand when you say that
words have no semantic meaning in isolation, but rather that meaning lives in the empty spaces between the letters

The visual appearance of the word is only an artifice to make the reader aware of what is the word (or the sentence) that should be made sense of. Writing m o u s e or m o u s e, may create more or less discomfort for the reader in realizing we are talking about a mouse, but then one still has to discern, in both cases, and through concepts, what that mouse is, and what it is doing in the overall sentence, which is not in any way impacted by how painful it was to get to grips with the code in the first place!


Here I should add that even in Cleric’s example of the thought ‘circle’, and although the way the example is expressed is very helpful to understand the void of perception and the act of filling it back with meaning, the conclusion with the hexagon feels less helpful, because it suggests that it’s then only a matter of coming up with six properly shaped pieces, slide them into the six voids, and that would be enough for a perfect match. It prompts the thought that, like in a circle-shaped Tetris, the whole block would then slot together and disappear.


My current understanding from PoF is that “what natural perceptual-cognitive processes do for us” is way more complex than - and actually also different from - filling spaces between letters, silence between notes or intersected shapes. Thinking creates experience by merging percept with concept, but because percepts get (by thinking) uniquely time-stamped, uniquely characterized with contours, with countless details, and countless interrelations, the match with (universal) concepts is practically never a perfect one. This is what keeps them up as percepts (I would even say, as ‘perceivables’) while an individualized thought-image is clicked and archived as memory for every moment we expose ourselves to the perceptual experience. Curiously, the impression I receive from your examples is that these are over-complicated examples (language and then music, I am coming to music) used to arrive at over-simplified conclusions. In a certain way I am struggling to follow your logic. I see it well in the general purpose and in the direction of the argumentation, I follow it well at that level, but if we zoom in on the details of your reasoning, then I’m lost, I am somehow missing what you are not saying.


About music, the first thing that makes me wonder why you chose music as an example of natural perceptual-conceptual process to use as a bridge to grasp mechanistic processes, is that unless we are playing or listening to live music, the general experience of music we most frequently have is indeed through digital media technology. I am not referring to the experience you suggest here with the 3 samples, because of course you didn’t have any other choice, but to the most common experience of music these days. But ok, let’s imagine live music, say an orchestra, playing Vivaldi’s Summer. We immediately get into complications with this example of musical performance. For instance, there is in reality no silent space between beats, notes and chords here. If we dissect the composition in groups of instruments, then yes, we find some silence, but that’s not the living experience of the performance. More importantly, the musical structure, the rhythm, is not what invites meaning in this percept. It's only one minor element of the meaning. The rhythm is the naked, geometrical, in a way neutral, repetitive framework to which the musical language, the phrase, is appended. The meaning is in the development of the phrase, in melody. This phrase can be long and articulated, or simple, square and repetitive, contrasted or nuanced, surprising or highly predictable… etcetera. It can take thousand different forms and there resides the meaning, not in the tempo and its see-throughs. On the same temporal structure, thousands of pieces of music have been written and thousand more could be written, with completely different meanings! To me, the liminal spaces of understanding music do exist, but are not literal spaces between beats notes and chords. They are not “exemplified by rhythmic thresholds”. They are conceptual liminal spaces, which, yes, develop in temporal form, but cannot be reduced to our grasping of the beat in the music. This is an incredible over-simplification! The liminal spaces are of very changing duration and path, and it's their unfolding that determines the transition between one state of being and the next.
It’s a little bit of the same problem I found in the previous example, with language. It must be no coincidence that music is a language, and the physical spaces that pace it are not the code, but only a framework that supports the unfolding of the code. So here again I feel music is a complex, difficult example from which over-simplified conclusions are drawn.

Getting to the 3 samples, here’s my thoughts. I don’t agree that the liminal spaces appear as a property ‘of the song’ in the form of paced openings in its rhythm that invite meaning. Rather, they arise in the thinking act of making sense of the song, at the conjunction of concept and percept. I see them as qualitative spaces in cognition. While I do have a preference - like you, I prefer Vivaldi’s Summer, the fast and furious of the three, in my opinion - I can make sense of all three songs with equal ‘ease’. I can enter each of these three worlds and understand them. By the way, the metal one with a very fast pace sounds monotone and slow to my ear, because of its somber and heavy vibe. The liminal spaces there - the changes in status that help us approach and grasp the music by probing its character - appear to me in longer spans, in a way that is quite independent from musical tempo. It’s a qualitative understanding that follows the unfolding of the phrase and explores the meaning in there, rather than in a flat geometrical temporal structure that is nearly the same in a thousand other songs!These peculiar, slower liminal spaces don’t make it easier or more difficult to apprehend the song, they only make it less pleasant for me in this case. But this is a matter of feeling, and how it personalizes the process, rather than pure cognition, I would imagine.


Finally, coming to the conclusion about the effect of mechanization, technology, and high-pace repetition on cognition. Unsurprisingly at this point, because I don’t recognize the strict correlation between the presence of comfortable open or silent spaces in perception (visual or temporal see-throughs) and the ease of filling it with meaning, I would confirm my initial thought. I definitely agree that our orientation to technology is over-indulgent and problematic, but in my view the problem with it actually resides in the preponderant role of abstraction, the force that underlies and determines technology, way more than it resides in its repetitive and mechanistic character itself.
Ashvin, I have to admit I am a bit saddened by not being able to concur as much as I would have liked here. Your thoughts in this essay have been very insightful and helpful in guiding my reflection in this matter and I am thankful for that, however I would have preferred to agree with not only the high level direction of the essay, which I do, but also with the detailed reasoning. I hope I am missing points that I’ll get later and that will allow me to better integrate these views.


A side note, on the evolution of language, a topic I’m interested in. This “History in English words” by Barfield seems an extraordinary book with a prodigious purpose! It definitely goes on my list. Having studied the old languages in highschool, all the provided examples of words were known to me, but I definitely want to see where he brings it in the book. If you have other works in mind with specific reference to the evolution of language, please recommend!

:
This is the goal towards which the sixth age of humanity will strive: the popularization of occult truth on a wide scale. That's the mission of this age and the society that unites spiritually has the task of bringing this occult truth to life everywhere and applying it directly. That's exactly what our age is missing.
Post Reply